Introduction
I do not care to discuss the term faith as it is used in common parlance. The New Testament concept is the one I care to analyze and capture. However, I will be making an appeal to Philo’s conception of faith. Given Philo’s importance for early Christianity, I think this is a natural appeal and not really in tension with my first desiderata of analyzing New Testament faith on its own terms—for instance, there are strong hints of influence, or at least hints of a common milieu,1 between Philo and the author of Hebrews in their respective discussions of the nature of faith.
The primary purpose of this writing is to probe whether New Testament faith extols a faith contrary to reason; whether, in the conception of the New Testament writers, it’s more noble, proper, or commendable to believe contrary to the evidence. This question will become more useful if we make a distinction and ask it again in light of the distinction.
The Distinction: Defeated Warrant vs Lessened Warrant
A belief with contrary evidence may be defeated by that contrary evidence or, alternatively, have merely less justification due to that contrary evidence. A defeated belief is one that is no longer rational to hold. A lessened belief is one that is still rational to hold, but less compelling and taking a hit to its warrant. For ease of illustration, we can think of these differences along probability lines.2
Defeated Warrant (DW): A belief that has lost its justification, falling below a 50% probability credence.
Lessened Warrant (LW): A belief that has a reduced justification in light of new evidence, but still possessing greater than a 50% probability credence.
The contention of this paper is that NT faith may suffer from LW but not DW. This contention needs to be substantiated.
Application to Scripture
Turning to Scripture, let’s apply the above distinction to Paul’s account of Abraham’s faith:
Without weakening in his faith, he faced the fact that his body was as good as dead—since he was about a hundred years old—and that Sarah’s womb was also dead.
(Rom. 4:19)
Abraham, “in the face of contrary evidence,”3 maintained his belief in God’s promise that he would have a child. So we have an evidential drop, a drop of warrant, and Paul commends Abraham for maintaining his belief in the face of this drop. Was this drop of the DW or LW persuasion? Take Abraham’s epistemic situation. He had witnessed miraculous confirmations of the promise, the miraculous and predicted destruction of two cities, and had met God personally on multiple occasions. Moreover, as is assumed through the Scriptural account, God provides us with an immediate epistemic warrant for both beliefs about God and for beliefs from God through the sensus divinitatis and testimonia of the Holy Spirit. I think this epistemic environment more than justifies Abraham’s faith in God’s promise. Moreover, I think that the contrary evidence of Abraham and Sarah’s biology are unlikely to overrule these streams of justification. So it seems clear, or at least plausible, that Abraham is suffering from mere LW and not DW.
I think particular focus needs to be placed on the testimony of the Holy Spirit. For the confirmation of the Christian religion, believers rely primarily on this internal witness that God provides through the activity of the Holy Spirit. Alvin Plantinga has provided a robust defense along Externalist lines of how this activity could provide an agent with warrant sufficient for knowledge, which, under times of trial like Abraham’s impotent body in the face of the promise, would place Abraham’s belief under at most LW and not under DW.
I think that’s right. But if we stopped here in our analysis of this and similar passages I think we’d be overlooking their central purpose. It’s at this point that I want to appeal to Philo. According to Philo, the struggle of faith isn’t so much an evidential struggle as it is a struggle between prioritizing that which is invisible over that which is visible. This struggle, for Philo, reveals that the believer is placing his trust in the invisible God, and not taking earthly visible reality as ultimate or determinative for the believer’s situation. Evidential matters do enter into the question for Philo, but only in a tangential way. These sort of tests of faith are primarily vehicles that reveal where the believer ultimately puts their trust, revealing that upon which they truly rely. They rely on God and not the world. They take God as ultimately determinative for their destiny and situation and not worldly circumstance.4
These considerations should lead to us to revise LW to better reflect the kind of LW that New Testament faith occasionally suffers:
Lessened Visible Warrant (LVW): Though LVW is an evidential drop, that is, a state-of-affairs that seems to suggest that God either isn’t good or isn’t providing, it’s the sort of drop that relies on taking situational creaturely powers as ultimate over us. These specific types of LW are temptations to idolatry, despair, or distraction based on what’s visible to our eyes.
LVW are, to some extent, occasional occurrences for the Christian. LVW serves a revelatory purpose in that it reveals the faith of the sufferers. For if they had faith in the world they would despair. But they did not despair, which reveals that they had faith in God. LVW can also produce character, strengthen faith, and show the world for the false idol that it is. It demonstrates exactly where the believer places their hope, who they worship. We can see this sort of use of LVW in 2 Cor. 1:9: “Indeed we felt that we had received the sentence of death so that we would not trust in ourselves but in God who raises the dead."
LVW can, of course, also serve a negative role in that it can highlight the double-mindedness of half-committed believers, believers who take worldly situations to be determinative and ultimate; i.e., Peter stepping out of the boat onto the water and Jesus’s response: “Why did you doubt?”.5 Peter was only half-relying upon the invisible God and was overcome by his immediate visible situation, being tempted to despair as he sank.
Hebrews XI
The goal of this section is to analyze Hebrews XI in light of the Philonic interpretative grid just provided. Here’s the relevant passage:
Now faith is confidence in what we hope for and assurance about what we do not see. This is what the ancients were commended for. By faith we understand that the universe was formed at God’s command, so that what is seen was not made out of what was visible.
This passage clearly stresses the importance of invisible realities to the life of faith. This fits well with what we just established on the Philonic take. Some translations render “assurance” as “conviction.” I think both words fit well in that they display a deep valuing and dependence on non-worldly realities—we can also see this theme a few verses back, in 10:34: “You . . . accepted with joy the confiscation of your possessions, because you know that you yourselves have a better and enduring possession.” The latter part of the passage, that “what is seen was not made out of what was visible” also, I think, contains an implicit disparagement of visible reality in that it highlights the dependency of the visible world on the deeper reality of the invisible spiritual world.
There are some commentators that take this passage to primarily describe faith as an organ, in that it is the means by which we know spiritual realities. I think that’s right, but I also think that the Philonic conception helps us to see in just what manner faith functions as such an instrument; which is via faith’s non-dependency on the world, in that it seeks out God and higher, nobler goals. It is through this character of faith that it functions as the means by which we know the spiritual world.
God’s Hiddenness
The problem of God’s hiddenness may seem distant from our current discussion, but pausing to reflect on it will reveal some important connections. Recall what exactly the problem is—that God, even though he provided us with evidence for his existence, could have provided us with even more evidence. God could have written “God exists” in the clouds every day. He could make an appearance on the daily news to announce his existence. But he doesn’t. I don’t think this is an undefeatable problem; but it is one that requires a response. And I think the response is going to be along the lines of seeing the value of LVW; God’s non-obviousness can produce a concerted effort to find him, an effort that may be valuable, that shows the tenacity of a person’s denial of the ultimacy of the world, seeking out a true and lasting value. God’s non-obviousness can produce character or draw us together. And so on. LVW have a similar purpose.
The problem of God’s hiddenness seems like it’s going to elicit a defense of something very close to LVWs, so it seems that Christians are already committed to the value and need of LVWs even prior to this account.6
The Cognitive Element of Faith
We’ve been talking about the virtuosity of belief-that, or cognitive faith. That cognitive faith could be virtuous or not has seemed odd to many philosophers. So we need to examine the depths here to get a better grasp of this. Some definitions that will prove helpful:
Belief-in (BI): An act of valuing
Belief-that (BT): An act of acknowledging
To be clear: Belief-that isn’t virtuous or noble according to Christianity. BT unaccompanied by BI is known in Christianity as mere historical faith and is possessed by even the demons.
Yet, in our discussion of Abraham, it seems that his belief-that God would give him an heir in the face of contrary evidence is the feature that Paul is extolling. So how do we reconcile this? Here’s a suggestion: BT can inherit a virtuous character if it is the product of a more fundamental BI. So BT has a sort of second-order virtuousness in certain situations, and I think Abraham’s BT is an example of this.
I’m not sure that’s right. I think the account given in the last paragraph can apply to the virtuousness of Abraham’s faith in the specific promises made to him, but I’m not thinking that the account should be generalized. For it is a doctrinal matter for Christians that God has given immediate epistemic knowledge of himself to all agents. So all agents possess BT. But some are resistive of the BT that they possess—unbelievers and demons. What BI can do in these cases is render the BT non-resistive. So it’s non-resistive BT that can be virtuous in this more general case.
Of course, we’re conflating the spheres of Abraham’s reliance on God for those specific promises with the sphere of a generalized salvific faith. There may be issues lurking in this conflation. I’m sure there are. But Paul himself seems to conflate them for illustrative purposes, so I’ll leave it be for now.
Is the Cognitive Element Necessary?
Given this sort of limitation on the importance of BT that we’ve been stressing, the question may arise whether faith requires or needs BT at all. Consider whether it’s possible to be a Hope-Theist:
Hope-Theist: Someone who positively disbelieves in the truth of Christianity but yet hopes that it is true.
A Hope-Theist would be an agent with BI but lacking BT. As stated in the last paragraph, BT is universal among agents given the way that God has designed the world. Our epistemic build leads us to an automatic belief-that God exists and the general outlines of the way in which he governs the world. This shows that BT is necessary as a matter of fact, that is, that all agents possess BT, so a Hope-Theist is not possible, as BI (which would be roughly the same as “hoping” for Christianity) erases resistive rejection of BT. But perhaps we’re after something a bit deeper as to why BT and BI should go together, so perhaps we need to go deeper than merely that it is the case that BT and BI go together to why they should go together.
One promising avenue as stated by Philo: “It is a grievous thing to merely hope for good things without also knowing that those good things will come about.” This provides at least some evidence that God would provide us with BT if we possessed BI. It is good for us to know that our hopes will come about, and we should, and naturally do, seek to increase our warrant for the belief that they will come about. Even Abraham, the paradigm example of faith, exhibited this nature: “But Abram replied, ‘Lord GOD, how can I know that I will possess it?’”. Those who hope for something will naturally look for confirmation that their hopes will take place, and there is nothing wrong with this attitude. And given the indelible traces of God’s existence in the created order, it seems that they will reach justified conclusions as a result of observing and reasoning about the created order.
Recall the Hope-Theist. He may go through the motions, attending Church, singing hymns, and so on. But if he doesn’t believe that Christianity could at least possibly be true, that it has at least some moderate possibility, then his behavior is a case of make-believe, of merely playing along. He may think it’s beautiful or neat, but he can’t take it seriously in his inner recess. So at least a marginal BT seems required to avoid the make-believe charge.
The last paragraph does open up the possibility of someone who, though they may not be said to believe in Christianity, that is, does not assign a probability credence greater than 50% to Christianity, may nevertheless hold open a slimmer chance for its truth. They may decide, out of the eminence of Christian values and its manner, and in light of their desperate lot in life on the one hand, that committing to Christianity and holding onto the small probability that it is true is worth doing. This person does not positively believe or disbelief in Christianity in the sense of BT, but holds to it in BI. I think this person is a real possibility and may legitimately be called a Christian.
It is, moreover, well within their rights to seek to increase the warrant that they have for Christian belief. They can seek out arguments and confirmations for the promises of the religion, just as Abraham, the Father of Faith, did also.
Doubting Thomas and the Big Chief
I want to consider wherein the wrongness of Thomas’ doubt consisted. I want to do this by comparing his attitude to that of a prisoner in an analogy provided by Richard Swinburne:
A man in prison may be told that he will be rescued by ‘The Big Chief’ from the outer yard of the prison, if he can get there at night. On balance, the prisoner does not believe this rumour; he does not think there is any such Big Chief. But the rumour has some plausibility; and the prisoner has no other hope of escaping. He believes that it is far more probable that he will attain his goal of escaping by acting on the assumption that the ‘Big Chief’ exists than by acting on any other assumption. So he steals a file, files away the bars of his cell, and squeezes through the cell window to get into the outer yard of the prison. He is liable to be punished when all this is discovered, unless by then he has succeeded in escaping. The prisoner is not inappropriately described as putting his trust in the Big Chief.
Thomas should have had a similar attitude to this prisoner. The problem with Thomas isn’t that he doubted but how much he doubted. Thomas may have thought that he had insufficient evidence to affirm the resurrection; but he should have, out of a noble desire, not have resorted to strong and willful denial of the resurrection. He should have instead, as the prisoner did the experiment, kept an open mind, preparing and hoping for the Big Chief, despite not having full belief in him. There was, after all, evidence possessed by Thomas. He had seen the prophetic fulfillments of Jesus, his various miracles, and of course the apostolic testimony to the resurrection. He may have thought he had insufficient evidence, but this resulted from placing too high an evidential value on his present sensible situation. Though he may have been incapable of definite belief at that point, he nevertheless should have fallen back to the position of the prisoner in the analogy, rather than strong and definite denial. This analogy draws out the character of the Hope-Theist.
A Calvin Quote
Let us also remember, that the condition of us all is the same with that of Abraham. All things around us are in opposition to the promises of God: He promises immortality; we are surrounded with mortality and corruption: he declares that he counts us just; we are covered with sins: He testifies that he is propitious and kind to us; outward judgments threaten his wrath. What then is to be done? We must with closed eyes pass by ourselves and all things connected with us, that nothing may hinder or prevent us from believing that God is true.
Notes
1. See, for example, Kenneth Schenck’s paper Philo and the Epistle to the Hebrews: Ronald Williamson’s Study after Thirty Years.
2. Throughout this paper I’m going to use “justification,” “warrant,” and “evidence” quite loosely and not really in view of their technical meanings.
3. This statement stems from the eminent commentator Douglas Moo in his study notes for the NIV Biblical Theology Study Bible.
4. I think the substance of this Philonic position also underlies Paul’s statement in 2 Cor. 5:7 that we “live by faith and not by sight.”
6. Just to be clear; just because God could have provided even stronger evidence for his existence does not negate the evidence that he has provided us. You can have good and strong evidence for a proposition and yet have even stronger evidence that is still possible but absent. If anything, that’s almost always the case.